I call this blog “Metaphorical Times” because I sense that the extreme divisions that are so characteristic of our society these days have reference to the nature of metaphor itself. I sense, both from my job teaching college students and my casual social relations with others, that we are losing an important means of understanding our world, through metaphor. Metaphor is essentially associative and synthetic, the opposite of so many of the opposites we are bombarded with these days.
So, what's a
metaphor? Well, whole books have been written on the topic, and
“experts” will argue the definition forever. But I have
developed a simple working definition of metaphor that I have found
is very helpful in everyday life—certainly not just in English
classrooms. In my definition, a metaphor is a linguistic association
of two different entities; usually one entity is a concrete image,
such as a rose, and the other one is an abstract idea, such as love.
To take it further, one element of a metaphor makes reference to a
physical entity that we can interact with, while the other element
reflects mental categories. (And, in this simple definition, a
simile is just a subset of metaphor, since it performs the same
function, but more openly.) So, when the late eighteenth-century
Scottish poet Robert Burns writes, “O, my Luve's like a red red
rose . . . ,” he is using the concrete image of a rose (of a very
red rose, to be precise) to describe his love—his experience of
loving a particular person. Why does he do this? For two reasons, I
think. First, he's probably struggling to understand his feelings,
and somehow his past experiences of a red rose help him to focus the
perhaps chaotic experience of love. Second, if Burns wants to convey
this confused state of being to another person (i.e., his
reader), he can best do so by referring to a physical thing in the
common experience of his reader, such as a red rose—an experience
many people share.
The more Burns
himself and we, the readers, have extensive experience with roses,
the more we will understand what Burns is trying to convey about his
love. It would be a careless poet, indeed, who would not take into
account that roses are not only considered to be among the most
beautiful productions of nature with a wonderful aroma, but that they
also have thorns, get diseased pretty easily, and die relatively
quickly (the flowers, anyway). Indeed, cultured roses these days
need a lot of human care to flourish. Only the rest of Burns' poem
can guide us on which physical characteristics of a rose he intends
to compare to his love--in other words, what his experience of this
love has been.
A rose as the
symbol for romantic love, especially a red rose, has become virtually
a cliché to us modern folk, who see pictures of roses everywhere
each February and at times buy or receive roses in the supermarket in
protective plastic sleeves, usually de-thorned. But how often do we
consider why it is a red rose that has come to express romantic
passion for us? Do we stop to consider how a common component of
passion is the rush of blood to the skin? Or that a person we feel
we love even more than ourselves is a person we value even more
highly than our own life force, our blood? In the non-fiction course
I taught last spring, as we were reading an essay on Georgia O'Keeffe
and looking at some of her erotic flower paintings, I asked the
students if they ever wondered why we tend to give flowers to
someone we have romantic feelings for. In the ensuing discussion, it
seemed that only one or two students knew or remembered that the
flower is the sexual part of a plant. Of course, not every young
person who walks into a florist and buys roses for his or her beloved
is thinking of buying vegetable sexual organs as a means of hopefully
seducing the receiver to have sex with him or her. The connection is
usually unconscious, but it's there by way of a long history of human
associations with flowers.
The immediate
conscious connection of concrete image and abstract idea has often
been lost in the social process of reducing real thing to symbol--the
narcotizing deception of the rose (or romantic love) as an eternal
ideal of wonderful feelings, rather than the real, beautiful, hurtful
natural thing it is. The latter form of knowledge—reality—wouldn't
help Hallmark sell cards so much, would it? Roland Barthes has
discussed this process of socializing nature, using the term
“mythology” to describe it:
“Holding as
a principle that man in a bourgeois society is at every turn plunged
into a false Nature,
[mythology] attempts to find again, under the assumed innocence of
the most unsophisticated
relationships, the profound alienation which this innocence is meant
to make one accept.
The unveiling which it carries out is therefore a political act. . .
. in this sense mythology
harmonizes with the world, not as it is, but as it wants to create
itself. . . .”1
The alienation
Barthes mentions here, as I take it, is our alienation from the
natural world as it really is.
We humans have
become so proficient through our verbal and technical manipulations
in defining and controlling nature that we are hardly conscious
anymore of the state of being we come from, both physically and
historically. We are so used to living within an artificial world of
society and culture (by artificial I mean man-made) that we easily
accept the Hallmark rose as close enough to the real thing—even as
superior to the real thing, since it doesn't convey any of the more
negative experiences one might have with a rose, or with love. But
in accepting the artificial image as, essentially, our domesticated
reality, and in increasingly not minding or even happily
participating in the weeding out of the real Nature, we dispossess
ourselves from physical reality. We are manipulated by social
markets to expect an “innocent” world, as Barthes puts it, when
really we have been made “innocent” (ignorant) by our increasing
distance from nature and therefore much more liable to be
disappointed and hurt—or to no longer feel deeply, in order to
avoid or deny the negative feelings that are not socially acceptable.
(This may seem like a silly example, but one time I was camping with
my family, a group from a nearby city in the opposite campsite
started throwing kerosene from styrofoam cups into their fire, to get
it blazing. The kerosene that dribbled from the cups away from the
fire caught, and the whole campsite was at risk. I have rarely been
so frightened by “innocence.”)
Anyway, what seems
to me to be at the heart of all the oppositions clattering around us
these days is that some people trust technology to save us from
everything—even to deliver us to another planet when we use up this
one. As Barthes puts it, for these people, “. . . Nature . . . is
nothing but a Usage” (271). In other words, some people trust to
the abstract and think our salvation lies in our increasing distance
from nature. In recent discussions of the Higgs boson, Robert Wright
has bravely said:
“I
personally continue to have no idea what the Higgs boson is. And I
think the physicists who 'understand'
what it is can do so only because they don't have the lay-person's
compulsion to think about
the world in ways that are ultimately metaphorical. Or, at least,
these physicists have dropped
the idea that to truly understand something is to have a
crystal-clear metaphor in your mind, a
metaphor that doesn't break down at any point and doesn't contain
internal contradictions.
For them, apprehending a purely mathematical description of
something is tantamount to
comprehending it.”2
I don't go so far
as to want “a crystal-clear metaphor,” because I think muddy
metaphors that make us think about what works and what doesn't are
far more valuable—like the natural rose and love. But Wright makes
an important point here—many technologically oriented people (even
pure mathematicians use technology) put their faith in the abstract,
in a realm we cannot really know because we cannot directly
experience it. Someday, they seem to believe, if we fund
technological exploration sufficiently, it will save us from
ourselves and from our rapidly degrading and disappointing physical
world.
On the other hand
are people who believe we are creatures of this Earth and should be
working to respect the earth and keep it healthy as a good physical
home for ourselves. Much of technology tends to spoil the earth,
making it a less pleasant home—and one in which we are more
dependent on the consolation of the Hallmark rose. These people tend
to believe that we should fund environmental protections and
universal health care and population control—dealing with real
elements of this real earth. Many of the oppositions we deal with
daily come from this largely unstated disagreement, I think. Are we
not disturbed by global warming or mass poverty or the extinction of
species because we are just going to chug off to another planet
someday, where we will be in technological control? Or are we going
to tend to the real experiences of abuse and suffering on this earth
so that we can go on living here into the far future, we hope? Are
we the creator or the creature?
If we can't think
metaphorically, we are doomed to do the former—to use up the earth
and then move on. If we can't think metaphorically of our constant
relationship to the natural world and what it tells us about
ourselves, then we cannot do the latter—the natural state of the
real world comes to have no stable meaning for us. Only through a
metaphorical unity of natural thing and our rationalizing,
abstracting human mind can we hope to deal with the very great
problems that predominantly abstract thinking has brought to this
world. I'll give Roland Barthes the last word:
“. . . I do
not yet see a synthesis between ideology and poetry (by poetry I
understand, in a very general
way, the search for the inalienable meaning of things.) . . . And yet
this is what we must seek: a
reconciliation between reality and men, between description and
explanation, between object
and knowledge.” (274)
1Roland
Barthes, “Myth Today,” in Mythologies [1957], transl.
Richard Howard and Annette Lavers (NY: Hill & Wang, 2012), 271.
Sorry for the name-dropping, but this is one of the few times a
French theorist makes sense to me! Following quotes from Barthes
are also from this source.
2Robert
Wright, “What This Higgs Boson Thing Really Means,” The
Atlantic on-line, 7/5/12.
No comments:
Post a Comment